3/31/14
Redo
Hope you like the clean, simple look. I'm planning on getting back to blogging, but in a more casual, quick style. No treatises, just comments on the passing scene or on what I'm reading/working on. We'll see how that turns out.
3/8/14
The right to an open present
That was a long blog break! I've been thinking of changing what I do at this blog, or starting a different one, or abandoning blogging...but for the moment, I'm going to stay the course (as "W" used to say).
Quick thought for the day. In procreative and parental ethics, philosophers are forever talking about a child's right to an open future. By appealing to that right all sorts of conclusions are reached, about matters as disparate as gender selection, circumcision, and religious education. The basic idea is: we should make procreative plans and parenting decisions that preserve our progeny's ability to choose among many different possible futures, upon reaching adulthood. The sheer multiplicity of possibilities isn't what's valuable (I take it), but being able to choose among many different possible futures. So, we are to create children and raise them in such a way that we protect their adult autonomy.
Why not, I wonder, also speak of a right to an open present? Would it really be OK to impose one trajectory on a child's life, up to age 18, so long as at 18 she burst out of childhood with lots of options? No, surely not. Granted, all that suppression of choice would probably yield a closed, or at least highly dysfunctional, future. But it seems bad to make all the choices for your child regardless of what the future will bring. It would be bad even if you knew your child wasn't going to live a long life, or the world was coming to an end. The childhood stage of life couldn't possibly go well if your parents chose everything for you--what you ate, what you wore, what shows you watched, what books you read. It's intriguingly awful to think about this--the child whose parents choose every article of clothing, plan every party, select every sandwich. That's bad already, I think, and not just because it's going to give the child a closed (or dysfunctaional) future.
Setting aside the closed/open talk, what seems to be true is that autonomy is part of the good life at ever stage of life, but what it should comprise changes with the child's development. Perhaps writers focus on the right to an open future because they think adult choices are the ones that matter most--choices of career, marriage partner, religion, etc. It's not worth thinking as much about choices a five or ten year old must be able to make for herself. This demoting of the issue of childhood autonomy can be part of a more general stance that sees childhood as not quite life yet -- as merely a preparation for things to come. You can make a case for that, but I think not a terribly convincing one.
Quick thought for the day. In procreative and parental ethics, philosophers are forever talking about a child's right to an open future. By appealing to that right all sorts of conclusions are reached, about matters as disparate as gender selection, circumcision, and religious education. The basic idea is: we should make procreative plans and parenting decisions that preserve our progeny's ability to choose among many different possible futures, upon reaching adulthood. The sheer multiplicity of possibilities isn't what's valuable (I take it), but being able to choose among many different possible futures. So, we are to create children and raise them in such a way that we protect their adult autonomy.
Why not, I wonder, also speak of a right to an open present? Would it really be OK to impose one trajectory on a child's life, up to age 18, so long as at 18 she burst out of childhood with lots of options? No, surely not. Granted, all that suppression of choice would probably yield a closed, or at least highly dysfunctional, future. But it seems bad to make all the choices for your child regardless of what the future will bring. It would be bad even if you knew your child wasn't going to live a long life, or the world was coming to an end. The childhood stage of life couldn't possibly go well if your parents chose everything for you--what you ate, what you wore, what shows you watched, what books you read. It's intriguingly awful to think about this--the child whose parents choose every article of clothing, plan every party, select every sandwich. That's bad already, I think, and not just because it's going to give the child a closed (or dysfunctaional) future.
Setting aside the closed/open talk, what seems to be true is that autonomy is part of the good life at ever stage of life, but what it should comprise changes with the child's development. Perhaps writers focus on the right to an open future because they think adult choices are the ones that matter most--choices of career, marriage partner, religion, etc. It's not worth thinking as much about choices a five or ten year old must be able to make for herself. This demoting of the issue of childhood autonomy can be part of a more general stance that sees childhood as not quite life yet -- as merely a preparation for things to come. You can make a case for that, but I think not a terribly convincing one.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)